There is still a strong relativism that pervades discussions of art. When the going gets tough, the relativist chimes in to say that these matters are hopeless, irresolvable, personal, essentially contested, etc. This is too bad, because there is plenty of rationality to be had.
There are standards to which we may appeal in basic categories descending in order of priority: Absolute, Objective, Intersubjective, and Dyadic.
Absolute
Identity, Non-Contradiction, and the Excuded middle. Without these we cannot rational discuss anything. Contradictions can prove anything and are ruled out as a matter of course. In addition, we can add in valid forms of formal reasoning. Modus Ponens is valid. Affirming the Consequent is not. Breaking these rules is a deal-breaker for discussion.
Objective
In addition to the bare-bones laws of logic, there are universal, if not absolute reasons to which we may turn. Inductive rules of reasoning also hold (e.g., typicality, tests of causality, signs), even if Hume has forever put induction on an awkward footing. In addition we can add dialectical rules which have good prima facie sense and strength, such as the principle of charity in interpretation. We might disagree about how the rule applies in a given case (how many cases before we can be assured that a generalization is not hasty?), but rule itself is secure.
Intersubjective
So far, we have not said anything about evaluating art, but this is where intersubjectivity comes in. The standards of one's time and place may be deployed as resources for evaluation. These standards offer presumptive proofs (i.e., defeasible proofs which might be overturned), but until such proofs appear, the presumptive reasons offered by intersubjective standards hold as good.
Dyadic
Worst case scenario, if two interlocutors find a shared claim in their commitment store (i.e., claims held to be true), then that claim need not be proved. Thus, it is not irrational that so many of our conversations involve sharing subjective takes with each other. Each point of agreement is a resource for both sides, be that claim factual, axiomatic, normative, etc. Of course, two people might be foolish and agree that the world is flat, so such agreements have limited application (if any) outside of the scope of a local discussion. That stated, such agreements are quite valuable in the context of an intense dyadic exchange.
If an intersubjectivity violates objective standards, then the objective standard takes precedence. In in looking for dyadic agreement someone contradicts themselves in terms of commitment, then the absolute rule of logic holds sway (i.e., one cannot play the subjectivist when caught out in a self-contradiction--at least one claim must be conceded). Thus, these categories offer a hierarchy for rational discussion.
We can and should have rational discussions about value and art. Such conversations are not easy. That is, however, why they are fun. It is the thrill of the attempt to see if any given assessment might stick.
NOTE: There is a rhetorical tendency to back away from an intractable conversation by invoking relativism. This allows both sides to save face, because no one is really wrong. As a device used to allow both parties to save face, the relativism thrust is polite. The problems begin, however, when the politeness is mistaken for a hard and fast rule that we are fooling ourselves when we talk about art. I don't believe we are.
Particular standards for evaluation are welcome below. What have you found "works" in rationally discussing art?
There are standards to which we may appeal in basic categories descending in order of priority: Absolute, Objective, Intersubjective, and Dyadic.
Absolute
Identity, Non-Contradiction, and the Excuded middle. Without these we cannot rational discuss anything. Contradictions can prove anything and are ruled out as a matter of course. In addition, we can add in valid forms of formal reasoning. Modus Ponens is valid. Affirming the Consequent is not. Breaking these rules is a deal-breaker for discussion.
Objective
In addition to the bare-bones laws of logic, there are universal, if not absolute reasons to which we may turn. Inductive rules of reasoning also hold (e.g., typicality, tests of causality, signs), even if Hume has forever put induction on an awkward footing. In addition we can add dialectical rules which have good prima facie sense and strength, such as the principle of charity in interpretation. We might disagree about how the rule applies in a given case (how many cases before we can be assured that a generalization is not hasty?), but rule itself is secure.
Intersubjective
So far, we have not said anything about evaluating art, but this is where intersubjectivity comes in. The standards of one's time and place may be deployed as resources for evaluation. These standards offer presumptive proofs (i.e., defeasible proofs which might be overturned), but until such proofs appear, the presumptive reasons offered by intersubjective standards hold as good.
Dyadic
Worst case scenario, if two interlocutors find a shared claim in their commitment store (i.e., claims held to be true), then that claim need not be proved. Thus, it is not irrational that so many of our conversations involve sharing subjective takes with each other. Each point of agreement is a resource for both sides, be that claim factual, axiomatic, normative, etc. Of course, two people might be foolish and agree that the world is flat, so such agreements have limited application (if any) outside of the scope of a local discussion. That stated, such agreements are quite valuable in the context of an intense dyadic exchange.
Hierarchy
If an intersubjectivity violates objective standards, then the objective standard takes precedence. In in looking for dyadic agreement someone contradicts themselves in terms of commitment, then the absolute rule of logic holds sway (i.e., one cannot play the subjectivist when caught out in a self-contradiction--at least one claim must be conceded). Thus, these categories offer a hierarchy for rational discussion.
We can and should have rational discussions about value and art. Such conversations are not easy. That is, however, why they are fun. It is the thrill of the attempt to see if any given assessment might stick.
NOTE: There is a rhetorical tendency to back away from an intractable conversation by invoking relativism. This allows both sides to save face, because no one is really wrong. As a device used to allow both parties to save face, the relativism thrust is polite. The problems begin, however, when the politeness is mistaken for a hard and fast rule that we are fooling ourselves when we talk about art. I don't believe we are.
Particular standards for evaluation are welcome below. What have you found "works" in rationally discussing art?